ThoK Notes |
Foundations of Knowledge |
www.KAhome.eu |
Top | Chapters | Home |
Before asking how we justify claims of knowledge in different areas, we need to consider what kind of thing we can base any knowledge on: there must be some basic pieces of knowledge that we are completely justified in accepting, without having proven or even argued that they are true; and then there must be means to arrive at further knowledge from those basic pieces of knowledge.
In this section, therefore, we shall consider sense experience and memory, which provide us with basic knowledge; and language, which is the means by which we can express propositions, to pass on and gain knowledge. And in the next section we shall consider logic and reasoning, which enable us to deduce propositions from other propositions, and thereby to expand our knowledge.
There are very few propositions which cannot possibly be wrong just because someone believes them – and certainly not enough of them to serve as a basis of all our knowledge.
We must therefore be content to accept the evidence of our senses and memory as basic knowledge, provided that there are no overriding considerations to the contrary.
Top | Chapters | Home |
Are there any other senses that you think should be included?
So primary qualities are really in the objects, whereas secondary qualities, as perceived sensations, are only in the observer. This led Locke to argue that some of our ideas give us genuine information about the reality 'out there,' (and hence knowledge,) while others do not.
a. | solidity | b. | taste | c. | extension | d. | odour | |||||
e. | number | f. | figure | g. | colour | h. | sound |
While the distinction between primary and secondary qualities might seem rather 'academic', not so important to how we lead our lives, it is related to another one: a proposition can be either objective, i.e. only about the state of the world, or subjective, i.e. depend on someone's judgment.
objective | subjective |
"He scored 125 on an IQ test." or "He always has high marks on tests." | "He is intelligent." |
"She gained 57% on the Maths test." | "She got 63% on her English Literature essay." |
However, the example of the Necker cube shows that perception is an active process of interpreting the information we receive through our senses and of making sense of it. In general, when we look at something, we are unconsciously 'guessing' or forming hypotheses about what we can see. Most of the time we don't realise this, because there isn't any problem. But with the Necker cube, there are two equally likely hypotheses which we can hold, so we 'flip' between the two.
"Perception is not determined simply by stimulus patterns; rather it is a dynamic searching for the best interpretation of the available data ... perception involves going beyond the immediately given evidence of the senses" (Gregory, 1966.) Perception is "the process of assembling sensations into a useable mental representation of the world;" it "creates faces, melodies, works of art, illusions etc. out of the raw material of sensation" (Coon, 1983.)
Since perception, then, is a process which not simply records sense data but selects from them, draws inferences from them and organises them, it is a process which can go wrong.
Traditional Zulus, who live in round houses and have circular arrangements to their villages, are not taken in by the illusion, it seems. |
Consider the following report: "When Colin Turnbull, an anthropologist, was studying pygmies in 1961, he took one of them, who had become a friend, out of the forest on a trip. The pygmies he was studying had spent their whole lives in the forest – they were known as the 'forest people' – so to go outside it and see for miles across the plains was a new experience. ... When he [the pygmy] saw a herd of buffalo in the distance, he thought they were ants and he refused to believe that they were buffalo because they looked so small" (Hayes and Orrell, Psychology, 1987, pp. 43f.) |
"Two of the African tribes studied, the Batoro and the Banyankole, were at the top of the illusion scale, that is, they were most likely to see it. They both live in high, open country where you can see for miles without interference; ... A third tribe, the Bete, who live in a jungle environment, were at the bottom of the scale – they were least likely to see the illusion of all the groups. Europeans and Americans tended to come somewhere inbetween the three African tribes" (Gross, Psychology, 1987, p. 127.) |
An account of some ways in which our perceptions are automatically organised is given by Gestalt theory (from Ger. Gestalt, figure, shape,) which says that we tend to perceive things as wholes which are more than the sums of the given parts. Amongst the principles according to which our experience is organised are the following:
But perception is affected by various extraneous factors as well, such as context and other situational variables (the 'perceptual set,') and motivation and emotion.
Two of the most powerful and effective of all human fears are the fear of failure and the fear of success. |
Now, the kinds of errors and distortions described above can affect not only our perception of the physical world, but also the beliefs on which we base our judgments. This is something we must bear in mind when we make claims to knowledge, and when we critically assess such claims.
In various areas of psychology, too, the question whether, or to what extent, certain of our abilities or characteristics are innate (hereditary) or whether they are acquired (i.e. due to the environment) has been hotly debated. In some cases the question is open to empirical investigation.
size of cube [cm] | 30 | 30 | 90 | 90 |
distance [m] | 1 | 3 | 1 | 3 |
head-turns [%] | 98 | 58 | 54 | 22 |
Eugenics, [of which Pearson later was professor at London University ! ] ... was essentially a political movement, overwhelmingly confined to the members of the bourgeoisie or middle classes, urging upon governments a programme of positive or negative actions to improve the genetic condition of the human race. Extreme eugenicists believed that the condition of man and society could be ameliorated only by the genetic improvement of the human race – by concentrating on encouraging valuable human strains (usually identified with the bourgeoisie or with suitably tinted races, such as the 'Nordic'), and eliminating undesirable strains (usually identified with the poor, the colonized or unpopular strangers).We are all aware of the consequences of such views being applied.Eric Hobsbawm, The Age of Empire, 1875 -1914, 1987.
That certain human characteristics are not only inherited but are unevenly distributed amongst different races is one of the justifications used by racists to support their views: many people are convinced that blacks are inherently less intelligent and more violent than whites, say – but also that they have 'a much better sense of rhythm.'
Some recent research, reported under the heading "Nurture strikes back," shows how the discussion is still going on:
Once upon a time, the only ideologically acceptable explanations of mental differences between men and women were cultural. ... Today, by contrast, biology tends to be an explanation of first resort in matters sexual.... Success at spatial tasks like this often differs between the sexes (men are better at remembering and locating general landmarks; women are better at remembering and locating food), so the researchers were not surprised to discover a discrepancy between the two. The test asked people to identify an "odd man out" object in a briefly displayed field of two dozen otherwise identical objects. Men had a 68% success rate. Women had a 55% success rate.
... However, ... they asked some of their volunteers to spend ten hours playing an action-packed, shoot-'em-up video game ... As a control, other volunteers were asked to play a decidedly non-action-packed game ... for a similar amount of time. Both sets were then asked to do the odd-man-out test again.
Among the ... [second group], there was no change in the ability to pick out the unusual. Among those who had played ... [the action-packed video game], both sexes improved their performance.
That is not surprising, given the different natures of the games. However, the improvement in the women was greater than the improvement in the men – so much so that there was no longer a significant difference between the two. Morever, ... when the volunteers were tested again after five months, both the improvement and the lack of difference between the sexes remained. ...
That has several implications. ... And a third is that although genes are important, upbringing matters, too. In this instance, exactly which bit of upbringing remains unclear. Perhaps it has to do with the different games that boys and girls play.
The Economist, September 8th 2007, pp 94f.
Top | Chapters | Home |
Just from these terms, try to give a more detailed description of what these involve and an example from your own experience of each of these.
A distinction commonly made, (e.g. in the two-process model of Atkinson and Shiffrin, 1968,) is that between sensory, short-term and long-term memory. While sensory memory gives us an accurate account of the environment as experienced by the sensory system, only a small fraction of all the information that impinges on our senses is stored long enough for us to use it, and only some of this is further processed and enters our long-term memory to be potentially retrievable in future. Short-term memory seems to have a capacity of only about seven (plus or minus two) bits of information, but 'chunking' can be used to expand that capacity; and information remains in short-term memory for only 15 to 30 seconds, but this can be extended through 'rehearsal' or repetition.
An alternative model (Craik and Lockhart, 1972) tries to account for apparent differences between the different kinds of memory in terms of 'levels of processing': how well something is remembered just depends on whether it has been processed
These different kind of processing can be seen at work when we try to remember a telephone number, say.
Carefully listen to a second list of words that is read out, but write down as many of them as you can recall only after having counted backwards: 99, 96, 93, ..., 0. Again, count for each of the items how many students in the class remembered it.
Repeat the experiment for the second set of letters.
Repeat the experiment for the second list of words.
It can be shown that like perception, memory is an active process, not just a recording and replaying: how much and what one remembers is affected by such things as the content, certain internal processes and extraneous factors; and so we cannot unsceptically accept claims of knowledge based on memory, either.
For a start, it seems that memory is an 'imaginative reconstruction' of experience and that memory itself is transformed at the time of retrieval.
Another study of the effect of language on memory was performed by Loftus and Loftus, in 1975. They showed subjects a film of a traffic accident, and then asked them questions about what they had seen. After a week, the subjects were asked about the film again. Loftus found that the way in which the questions were asked had quite an effect on what the subjects remembered. For instance: one group of subjects was asked, immediately after seeing the film, "How fast were the cars going when they hit each other?" The other group of subjects was asked, "How fast were the cars going when they smashed into each other?" When they were tested later, the subjects were asked if they had seen any broken glass in the film. (There hadn't been any.) Those subjects who had heard the word "smashed" remembered seeing broken glass scattered around after the accident. In fact, their memory of the accident was of much a more serious one than in the other subjects' memories, even though they had both seen the same film. So it seems that, when we are asking someone to remember something, we have to be very careful that we do not accidentally say things which will distort their memories. It is for this reason that people are concerned about 'leading questions' in court, or in the police questioning of witnesses.Nor is our memory immune from the processes by which we continually try to make sense of what is around us – and if the information does not quite fit then we will alter it, without noticing, so that it does. This effect is now called 'effort after meaning,' and is well demonstrated in a study by Bartlett (1932):Hayes and Orrell, Psychology, 1987, pp. 169 f.
In serial reproduction, one subject reproduces the original story etc., then a second subject has to reproduce the first reproduction and so on until six or seven reproductions have been made. The method was meant to duplicate, to some extent, the process by which rumours and gossip are spread or legends passed from generation to generation.One of the best-known pieces of material Bartlett used was a North-American Indian folk-tale ..., which is difficult for non-Indian peoples because of its style and some of its unfamiliar content and underlying beliefs and conventions. ...
- The story becomes noticeably shorter; e.g. Bartlett found that after 6 or 7 reproductions, it shrank from 330 to 180 words.
- Despite it becoming shorter, and details becoming omitted, the story becomes more coherent; no matter how distorted it might become, it remains a story because subjects are interpreting the story as a whole, both listening to it and retelling it.
- It also becomes more conventional, that is, it retains only those details which can be easily assimilated to the shared past experience and cultural background of the subjects.
- It becomes more clichéd, that is, any particular or individual interpretations tend to be dropped.
Gross, Psychology, 1987, pp. 175 f.
In a study in 1981, he asked subjects to keep a diary for a week and to note down all the things which happened to them which were either pleasant or unpleasant. When the week was over, the subjects were put into a weak hypnotic trance and asked to remember that week. Before that, how-ever, it was suggested to them either that they were in a good mood or that they were in a bad mood. The subjects who were in a good mood remembered far more of the pleasant things that had happened to them that week, while the subjects who were in a bad mood remembered far more of the bad things.And again, these effects are not just theoretical, a matter for psychologists to investigate, they are of immediate relevance to our every-day beliefs and everyone's prejudices, as the following report on an experiment shows.Hayes and Orrell, Psychology, 1987, p. 172.
The Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology ... reported an experiment with people known to be either strongly pro- or anti-Democratic [-- relating to one of the two main parties in the US.] All heard a ten-minute speech on national affairs. Half of the material was carefully slanted to be pro-Democratic, and half slanted to be anti-Democratic. The people were told they were being tested on their memory. Twenty-one days later they were tested on the material. It was found that people's memories were 'significantly better' in recalling material that harmonized with their own political viewpoint or 'frame of reference'. There was a clear tendency for them to forget the material that did not harmonize with their own preconceived notions.Vance Packard, The Hidden Persuaders, 1957, p. 152.
Top | Chapters | Home |
The same applies to language, which at first sight is merely a 'harmless' tool for expressing and communicating knowledge. However, on further investigation it becomes clear that the language we use not only serves to express our thoughts but may affect or limit them as well.
Thus, our language, though it appears to be a 'transparent' means by which we can express more or less precisely what we want to say, always carries implicit meanings and expresses some values as well – be they ours, or those of society at large. Most of the time we are not at all aware of this hidden content. So when we discuss what our knowledge is based on, we must always ask critically about what is implied but not stated.
Oppressive language does more than represent violence; it is violence; does more than represent the limits of knowledge; it limits knowledge. Whether it is obscuring state language or the faux-language of mindless media; whether it is the proud but calcified language of the academy or the commodity driven language of science; whether it is the malign language of law-without-ethics, or language designed for the estrangement of minorities, hiding its racist plunder in its literary cheek – it must be rejected, altered and exposed. It is the language that drinks blood, laps vulnerabilities, tucks its fascist boots under crinolines of respectability and patriotism as it moves relentlessly toward the bottom line and the bottomed-out mind. Sexist language, racist language, theistic language – all are typical of the policing languages of mastery, and cannot, do not permit new knowledge or encourage the mutual exchange if ideas.A perhaps less serious example of this are what Bertrand Russell (1872-1970) called "emotive conjugations," such asToni Morrison, "Nobel Lecture," 1993.
-- in each case the same situation is described, but our way of putting it depends on who is talking to whom, and the implications are quite different.
I have reconsidered, We are firm, you have changed your mind, you are obstinate, he has gone back on his word. they are pig-headed.
A rather more obvious example of the value-ladenness of language comes from the time of the Gulf war, when one newspaper published the following comparison of how the participants on the two sides and the events of the war had been described in the British press in the previous week.
- We have ...
- reporting guidelines
- press briefings
- We ...
- take out, suppress
- eliminate, neutralise, decapitate
- dig in
- We launch ...
- first strikes
- pre-emptively
- Our men are ...
- boys, lads
- Our boys are ...
- professional
- lion-hearts
- cautious
- dare-devils
- loyal
- desert rats
- resolute
- Our boys are motivated by ...
- an old-fashioned sense of duty
- Israeli non-retaliation is ...
- an act of great statesmanship
- Our missiles cause ...
- collateral damage
- Our planes ...
- suffer a high rate of attrition
- fail to return from missions
- They have ...
- censorship
- propaganda
- They ...
- destroy
- kill
- cower in their foxholes
- They launch ...
- sneak missile attacks
- without provocation
- Their men are ...
- troops, hordes
- Theirs are ...
- brainwashed
- paper tigers
- cowardly
- cannon fodder
- blindly obedient
- mad dogs
- ruthless
- Their boys are motivated by ...
- fear of Saddam
- Iraqi non-retaliation is ...
- blundering/cowardly
- Their missiles cause ...
- civilian casualties
- Their planes ...
- are shot out of the sky
- are zapped
The Guardian, 24.01.1991.
In its strong version, the hypothesis of linguistic relativity states that for somebody to be able to think of something, his language has to contain the words for it. However, a considerable amount of cross-cultural work has shown that this is not so. For example, members of the Dani-tribe, whose language has only two colour-words, were no less good at making colour distinctions than people with 11 words for different colours in their language.
The weaker version of the hypothesis is rather more acceptable: it states that having certain words available in one's language, and a certain grammar, predisposes one to make sense of one's experiences in a certain way. Having 24 different words for snow in their language, the Lapps will be better at perceiving fine differences between different conditions in winter than I. (According to Steven Pinker, in The Language Instinct, 1994, that number is vastly exaggerated, the result of 'inflation,' as original reports were cited and re-cited by later writers.)
Thus, the MIT sociologist Sherry Turkle, talking about 'artificial life', or life simulated by computer programs, points out that
Calling a game Life does not make it alive. Calling a computational object an organism or a robotics device a creature does not make them alive either. Yet the use of such terms is seductive.The language we use to describe a science frames its objects and experiments, and, in a certain sense, tells us what to think of them. Sometimes we invent the language after we have the objects and have done the experiments. In the case of artificial life, the language existed before the birth of the discipline.
Life on the Screen, 1995, p. 156.
"Say in your own words what it is that the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis states, drawing on the three readings for examples."
Text a.:"Human beings do not live in the objective world alone, nor alone in the world of social activity as ordinarily understood, but are very much at the mercy of the particular language which has become the medium of expression for their society. It is quite an illusion to imagine that one adjusts to reality essentially without the use of language and that language is merely an incidental means of solving specific problems of communication or reflection. The fact of the matter is that the 'real world' is to a large extent unconsciously built up on the language habits of the group. ... We see and hear and otherwise experience very largely as we do because the language habits of our community predispose certain choices of interpretation." Edward SapirThere will probably be general assent to the proposition that an accepted pattern of using words is often prior to certain lines of thinking and forms of behavior, but he who assents often sees in such a statement nothing more than a platitudinous recognition of the hypnotic power of philosophical and learned terminology on the one hand or of catchwords, slogans and rallying cries on the other. To see only thus far is to miss the point of one of the most important interconnections which Sapir saw between language, culture and psychology, and succinctly expressed in the introductory quotation. It is not so much in these special cases of language as in its constant ways of arranging data and its most ordinary everyday analysis of phenomena that we need to recognize the influence it has on other activities, cultural and personal.The Name of the Situation as Affecting Behavior
I came in touch with an aspect of this problem before I had studied under Dr. Sapir, and in a field usually considered remote from linguistics. It was in the course of my professional work for a fire insurance company, in which I undertook the task of analyzing many hundreds of reports of circumstances surrounding the start of fires, and in some cases, of explosions. My analysis was directed towards purely physical conditions, such as defective wiring, presence or lack of air spaces between metal flues and woodwork, etc., and the results were presented in these terms. Indeed it was undertaken with no thought that any other significances would or could be revealed. But in due course it became evident that not only a physical situation qua physics, but the meaning of that situation to people, was sometimes a factor, through the behavior of the people, in the start of the fire. And this factor of meaning was clearest when it was a linguistic meaning, residing in the name or the linguistic description commonly applied to the situation. Thus, around a storage of what are called "gasoline drums," behavior will tend to a certain type, that is great care will be exercised; while around a storage of what are called "empty gasoline drums," it will tend to be different – careless, with little repression of smoking or of tossing cigarette stubs about. Yet the "empty" drums are perhaps the more dangerous, since they contain explosive vapor. Physically the situation is hazardous, but the linguistic analysis according to regular analogy must employ the word 'empty,' which inevitably implies lack of hazard. The word 'empty' is used in two linguistic patterns: (1) as a virtual synonym for 'null and void, negative, inert,' (2) applied in analysis of physical situations without regard to, e.g., vapor, liquid vestiges, or stray rubbish, in the container. The situation is named in one pattern (2) and the name is then "acted out" or "lived up to" in another (1), this being a general formula for the linguistic conditioning of behavior into hazardous forms.In a wood distillation plant the metal stills were insulated with a composition prepared from limestone and called at the plant "spun limestone." No attempt was made to protect this covering from excessive heat or the contact of flame. After a period of use, the fire below one of the stills spread to the "limestone," which to everyone's great surprise burned vigorously. Exposure to acetic acid fumes from the stills had converted part of the limestone (calcium carbonate) to calcium acetate. This when heated in a fire decomposes, forming inflammable acetone. Behavior that tolerated fire close to the covering was induced by use of the name "limestone," which because it ends in "-stone" implies non-combustibility. ...
An electric glow heater on the wall was little used, and for one workman had the meaning of a convenient coathanger. At night a watchman entered and snapped a switch, which action he verbalized as 'turning on the light.' No light appeared, and this result he verbalized as 'light is burned out.' He could not see the glow of the heater because of the old coat hung on it. Soon the heater ignited the coat, which set fire to the building. ...
A drying room for hides was arranged with a blower at one end to make a current of air along the room and thence outdoors through a vent at the other end. Fire started at a hot bearing on the blower, which blew the flames directly into the hides and fanned them along the room, destroying the entire stock. This hazardous setup followed naturally from the term 'blower' with its linguistic equivalence to 'that which blows,' implying that its function necessarily is to 'blow.' Also its function is verbalized as 'blowing air for drying,' overlooking that it can blow other things, e.g., flames and sparks. In reality, a blower simply makes a current of air and can exhaust as well as blow. It should have been installed at the vent end to draw the air over the hides, then through the hazard (its own casing and bearings), and thence outdoors. ...
Such examples, which could be greatly multiplied, will suffice to show how the cue to a certain line of behavior is often given by the analogies of the linguistic formula in which the situation is spoken of, and by which to some degree it is analyzed, classified, and allotted its place in that world which is "to a large extent unconsciously built up on the language habits of the group." And we always assume that the linguistic analysis made by our group reflects reality better than it does.
Grammatical Patterns as Interpretations of Experience
The linguistic material in the above examples is limited to single words, phrases, and patterns of limited range. One cannot study the behavioral compulsiveness of such material without suspecting a much more far-reaching compulsion from large-scale patterning of grammatical categories, such as plurality, gender and similar classifications (animate, inanimate, etc.), tenses, voices and other verb forms, classifications of the type of "parts of speech," and the matter of whether a given experience is denoted by a unit morpheme, an inflected word, or a syntactical combination. A category such as number (singular vs. plural) is an attempted interpretation of a whole large order of experience, virtually of the world or of nature; it attempts to say how experience is to be segmented, what experience is to be called "one" and what "several." But the difficulty of appraising such a far-reaching influence is great because of its background character, because of the difficulty of standing aside form our own language, which is a habit and a cultural non est disputandum, and scrutinizing it objectively. And if we take a very dissimilar language, this language becomes a part of nature, and we even do to it what we have already done to nature. We tend to think in our own language in order to examine the exotic language. Or we find the task of unraveling the purely morphological intricacies so gigantic, that it seems to absorb all else. Yet the problem, though difficult, is feasible; and the best approach is through an exotic language, for in its study we are at long last pushed willy-nilly out of our ruts. Then we find that the exotic language is a mirror held up to our own.In my study of the Hopi language, what I now see as an opportunity to work on this problem was first thrust upon me before I was clearly aware of the problem. The seemingly endless task of describing the morphology did finally end. Yet it was evident, especially in the light of Sapir's lectures on Navaho, that the description of the language was far from complete. I knew for example the morphological formation of plurals, but not how to use plurals. It was evident that the category of plural in Hopi was not the same thing as in English, French, or German. Certain things that were plural in these languages were singular in Hopi. The phase of investigation which now began consumed nearly two more years.
The work began to assume the character of a comparison between Hopi and western European languages. It also became evident that even the grammar of Hopi bore a relation to Hopi culture, and the grammar of European tongues to our own "Western" or "European" culture. And it appeared that the interrelation brought in those large subsummations of experience by language, such as our own terms 'time,' 'space,' 'substance,' and 'matter.' Since, with respect to the traits concerned, there is little difference between English, French, German, or other European languages, with the possible (but doubtful) exception of Balto-Slavonic and non-Indo-European, I have lumped these languages into one group called SAE, or "Standard Average European."
That portion of the whole investigation here to be reported may be summed up in two questions: (1) Are our own concepts of 'time,' 'space,' and 'matter' given in substantially the same form by experience to all men, or are they in part conditioned by the structure of particular languages? (2) Are there traceable affinities between (a) cultural and behavioral norms and (b) large-scale linguistic patterns? (I should be the last to pretend that there is anything so definite as "a correlation" between culture and language, and especially between ethnological rubrics such as 'agricultural, hunting,' etc., and linguistic ones like 'inflected,' 'synthetic,' or 'isolating.') When I began the study, the problem was by no means so clearly formulated, and I had little notion that the answers would turn out as they did.
Plurality and Numeration in SAE and Hopi
In our language, that is SAE, plurality and cardinal numbers are applied in two ways: to real plurals and to imaginary plurals. Or more exactly, if less tersely: perceptible spatial aggregates and metaphorical aggregates. We say 'ten men' and also 'ten days.' Ten men either are or could be objectively perceived as ten, ten in one group perception – ten men on a street corner, for instance. But 'ten days' cannot be objectively experienced. We experience only one day, today; the other nine (or even all ten) are something conjured up from memory or imagination. If 'ten days' be regarded as a group it must be as an "imaginary," mentally constructed group. Whence comes this mental pattern? Just as in the case of the fire-causing errors, from the fact that our language confuses the two different situations, has but one pattern for both. ...... A 'length of time' is envisioned as a row of similar units, like a row of bottles.
In Hopi there is a different linguistic situation. Plurals and cardinals are used only for entities that form or can form an objective group. There are no imaginary plurals, but instead ordinals used with singulars. Such an expression as 'ten days' is not used. The equivalent statement is an operational one that reaches one day by a suitable count. 'They stayed ten days' becomes 'they stayed until the eleventh day' or 'they left after the tenth day.' 'Ten days is greater than nine days' becomes 'the tenth day is later than the ninth.' Our "length of time" is not regarded as a length but as a relation between two events in lateness. Instead of our linguistically promoted objectification of that datum of consciousness we call 'time,' the Hopi language has not laid down any pattern that would cloak the subjective "becoming later" that is the essence of time. ...
Some Impresses of Linguistic Habit in Western Civilization
... Our objectified view of time is, however, favorable to historicity and to everything connected with the keeping of records, while the Hopi view is unfavorable thereto. The latter is too subtle, complex, and everdeveloping, supplying no ready-made answer to the question of when "one" event ends and "another" begins. When it is implicit that everything that ever happened still is, but is in a necessarily different form from what memory or record reports, there is less incentive to study the past. As for the present, the incentive would be not to record it but to treat it as "preparing." But our objectified time puts before imagination something like a ribbon or scroll marked off into equal blank spaces, suggesting that each be filled with an entry. Writing has no doubt helped toward our linguistic treatment of time, even as the linguistic treatment has guided the uses of writing. Through this give-and-take between language and the whole culture we get, for instance:
- Records, diaries, bookkeeping, accounting, mathematics stimulated by accounting.
- Interest in exact sequence, dating, calendars, chronology, clocks, time wages, time graphs, time as used in physics.
- Annals, histories, the historical attitude, interest in the past, archaeology, attitudes of introjection toward past periods, ...
It is clear how the emphasis on "saving time" which goes with all the above and is a very obvious objectification of time, leads to a high valuation of "speed," which shows itself a great deal in our behavior ...
Historical Implications
How does such a network of language, culture, and behavior come about historically? Which was first: the language patterns or the cultural norms? In the main they may have grown up together, constantly influencing each other. But in this partnership the nature of the language is the factor that limits free plasticity and rigidifies channels of development in the more autocratic way. This is so, because language is a system, not just an assemblage of norms. Large systematic outlines can change to something really new only very slowly, while many other cultural innovations are made with comparative quickness. Language thus represents the mass-mind; it is affected by inventions and innovations, but affected little and slowly, whereas to inventors and innovators it legislates with the degree immediate.from Benjamin Lee Whorf, "The Relation of Habitual
Thought and Behavior to Language," 1941.Text c.:
The Pirahã, a group of hunter-gatherers who live along the banks of the Maici River in Brazil, use a system of counting called "one-two-many". In this, the word for "one" translates to "roughly one" (similar to "one or two" in English), the word for "two" means "a slightly larger amount than one" (similar to "a few" in English), and the word for "many" means "a much larger amount". In a paper just published in Science, Peter Gordon of Columbia University uses his study of the Pirahã and their counting system to try to answer a tricky linguistic question.
This question was posed by Benjamin Lee Whorf in the 1930s. Whorf studied Hopi, an Amerindian language very different from the Eurasian languages that had hitherto been the subject of academic linguistics. His work led him to suggest that language not only influences thought but, more strongly, that it determines thought.
While there is no dispute that language influences what people think about, evidence suggesting it determines thought is inconclusive. For example, in 1972, Eleanor Rosch and Karl Heider investigated the colour-naming abilities of the Dani people of Indonesia. The Dani have words for only two colours: black and white. But Dr Rosch and Dr Heider found that, even so, Dani could distinguish and comprehend other colours. That does not support the deterministic version of the Whorf hypothesis.
While recognising that there are such things as colours for which you have no name is certainly a cognitive leap, it may not be a good test of Whorf's ideas. Colours, after all, are out there everywhere. Numbers, by contrast, are abstract, so may be a better test. Dr Gordon therefore spent a month with the Pirahã and elicited the help of seven of them to see how far their grasp of numbers extended.
Using objects with which the participants were familiar (sticks, nuts and – perhaps surprisingly – small batteries), he asked his subjects to perform a variety of tasks designed to measure their ability to count. Most of these tests involved the participant matching the number and layout of a group of objects that Dr Gordon had arranged on a table.
The tests began simply, with a row of, say, seven evenly spaced batteries. Gradually, they got more complicated. The more complicated tests included tasks such as matching numbers of unevenly spaced objects, replicating the number of objects from memory, and copying a number of straight lines from a drawing.
In the tests that involved matching the number and layout of objects they could see, participants were pretty good when faced with two or three items, but found it harder to cope as the number of items rose. Once it was beyond eight, they were getting it right only three-quarters of the time. The only exception was in those tests that used unevenly spaced objects – an arrangement that can be perceived as a group of clusters. Here, performance fell off when the number of objects was six, but shot up again when it was between seven and ten. Dr Gordon suggests that the participants used a "chunking" strategy, counting the clusters and the numbers of objects within each cluster separately.
Things were worse when the participants had to remember the number of objects in a layout and replicate it "blind", rather than matching a layout they could see. In this case the success rate dropped to zero when the number of items became, in terms of their language, "many". And line drawing produced the worst results of all – though that could have had as much to do with the fact that drawing is not part of Pirahã culture as it did with the difficulties of numerical abstraction. Indeed, Dr Gordon described the task of reproducing straight lines as being accomplished only with "heavy sighs and groans".
from "Language Barriers," The Economist,
August 21st 2004.
Top | Chapters | Home |
While we might speak of our 'mother-tongue' (and children do receive most of their early language skills from their mothers,) the arbiters of 'correct' language are mostly highly-educated white men: "Every language reflects the prejudices of the society in which it evolved. Since English, through most of its history, evolved in a white, Anglo-Saxon patriarchal society, no one should be surprised that its vocabulary and grammar frequently reflect attitudes that exclude or demean minorities and women. But we are surprised" (Casey Miller and Kate Swift, 1981.)
In acknowledgment of the importance of an awareness of this inbuilt linguistic bias and the need to reconstruct parts of our language without losing its spontaneity and accessibility, several sets of guidelines for non-oppressive language have been written, particularly in the area of non-sexist language. Not surprisingly there has been resistance to and scorn for such changes, but such usages as "he or she," or "humanity" instead of "mankind," are rapidly gaining ground. ... Other oppressive bias in language has received less attention, but the absolute correctness of correct English in the face of perfectly acceptable alternatives is in question: "Ain nothin in a long time lit up the English teaching profession like the current hassle over Black English" (Geneva Smitherman, Black Scholar, 1973.)
A relatively recent addition to the ways in which we receive language are the mass media which, while at least tacitly purporting to relate the truth, often simplify and distort language at the same time as introducing bias and disinformation. "Mass communication communicates massively: its language lacks precise articulation and avoids demanding terms; it argues for the kind of behaviour in life which will make a 'good programme' ... Television writes our scripts and it thus gives us back our language in a verisimilitudinous recension, docked of amateurish or embarrassing passions or obsessions which might cause our audience to switch off. If, lacking TV, you want a phrasebook of the prevailing television cant, why not simply turn on a friend?" (Frederic Raphael, in Leonard Michaels and Christopher Ricks (ed,) 1980.) ... Green-thinkers have vital things to say, and the way we say them is crucial to our cause: "The need today, as always, is to be in command of language, not used by it, and so the challenge is to find clear, convincing, graceful ways to say accurately what we want to say" (Casey Miller and Kate Swift, 1981.)
Top | Chapters | Home |
The 'experiments' that are suggested should be considered as a learning activity for the whole class, and good experimental practice should be discussed, such as that when there are two tasks, half of the students should have one task first, the others the other task.
If a sense organ is like a speedometer which shows the speed of a car in analogue form, and a sensation is a particular reading, then perception is like a process which converts the information into one of four tones, depending on which of four ranges the speed is in. (E.g. speed from 0 to 127 km/h: 7 bits of information; whether 0 to 31 km/h, 32 to 63 km/h, etc.: only 2 bits.)
If my knowledge that the blue ball is between the red and the yellow ball is based on sensation, I must know more, viz. on which sides the red and the yellow balls are. (This lends itself to a demonstration, where only one student can see an arrangement behind a screen – he will always know more than he can describe to the others, though there may be nothing he cannot tell.)
"There is a limit to the rate at which human subjects can process information ... [and] to how much information we can extract from our sensory experience ... Our sensory experience is informationally rich and profuse in a way that our cognitive utilization of it is not. ... It is this fact that makes the sensory representation more like a picture of, and the consequent belief a statement about, the source" (Dretske, "Sensation and Perception," 1982, pp. 157f, 160.)
Exercise 1.4.:
Asking for the positions of the five cards in each set to be recorded only serves to provide an ostensible objective for the experiment.
I: | II: | |
seat, farming, whale, segment, UWC flow, drain, banquet, dance, dolphin fast, plane, glue, border, prevented |
sex, failing, whore, suicide, AIDS fuck, death, bastard, drugs, dentist fart, penis, guts, bloody, perverted |
The reason may be that the letter has a different sound in the word "of", and that what we see is affected by our quietly reading the sentence to ourselves.
In the nature-nurture debate one needs to consider that if knowledge is innate it may take the form of certain concrete faculties.
For instance, like other species, man is capable of a mental representation of outside reality: e.g. bats do not use their sonar to orientate themselves in their usual territory because they have such a representation of it, and so they can actually fly into small obstacles that have not been there before. This ability to represent reality in some way is presumably the result of evolution, and such as to serve the individuals of the species well.
In the case of man, one aspect of this may be to distinguish in all perceptions a foreground and a background. Whether or not we can say on this basis that we have some knowledge (for instance of the existence of concrete objects) that we are born with may be a matter for discussion.
It has been argued, following Chomsky's lead, that man's ability to learn a language is innate, and even that there is an instinct, operating up to about age ten, to use certain perceptions, viz. of the speech of others, to build up a mental grammar, vocabulary and phonology of one's mothertongue. This seems to be the only way to account for a wide range of observations, notably the ability of children to learn a language 'fully', despite the very limited input they have, especially if the previous generation only speaks a pidgin-language, say. This does not mean that any particular language is innate. (Steven Pinker, The Language Instinct, 1994.)
|
|
I: | chicken, John, trumpet, France, red, Charles, Japan, zebra, Mike, cow, green, piano, Australia, brown, Steven, whale, orange, guitar, Canada, cello. |
II: | Spanish, Russian, Chinese, Greek, physics, art, maths, history, hammer, saw, screwdriver, axe, soccer, tennis, rugby, chess, boat, car, plane lorry.) |
Many people's list will include the word "sleep", which was not actually read out: 'effort after meaning.'
... There is and will be rousing language to keep citizens armed and arming; ... stirring, memorializing language to mask the pity and waste of needless death. There will be more diplomatic language to countenance rape, torture, assassination. ... there will be more of the language of surveillance disguised as research; of politics and history calculated to render the suffering of millions mute; language glamorized to thrill the dissatisfied and bereft into assaulting their neighbors; arrogant pseudo-empirical language crafted to lock creative people into cages of inferiority and hopelessness.Below is the full list of juxtapositions in the article from The Guardian:
- We have ...
- Army, Navy and Air Force
- reporting guidelines
- press briefings
- We ...
- take out
- suppress
- eliminate
- neutralise or decapitate
- dig in
- We launch ...
- first strikes
- pre-emptively
- Our men are ...
- boys
- lads
- Our boys are ...
- professional
- lion-hearts
- cautious
- confident
- heroes
- dare-devils
- young knights of the skies
- loyal
- desert rats
- resolute
- brave
- Our boys are motivated by ...
- an old-fashioned sense of duty
- Israeli non-retaliation is ...
- an act of great statesmanship
- Our missiles cause ...
- collateral damage
- Our PoWs are ...
- gallant boys
- George Bush is ...
- at peace with himself
- resolute
- statesman-like
- Our planes ...
- suffer a high rate of attrition
- fail to return from missions
- They have ...
- a war machine
- censorship
- propaganda
- They ...
- destroy
- destroy
- kill
- kill
- cower in their foxholes
- They launch ...
- sneak missile attacks
- without provocation
- Their men are ...
- troops
- hordes
- Theirs are ...
- brainwashed
- paper tigers
- cowardly
- desperate
- cornered
- cannon fodder
- bastards of Baghdad
- blindly obedient
- mad dogs
- ruthless
- fanatical
- Their boys are motivated by ...
- fear of Saddam
- Iraqi non-retaliation is ...
- blundering/cowardly
- Their missiles cause ...
- civilian casualties
- Their PoWs are ...
- overgrown school children
- Saddam Hussein ...
- demented
- defiant
- an evil monster
- Their planes ...
- are shot out of the sky
- are zapped
Exercise 3.2.:
Do you believe if I say that language can make a person different? What I mean is this. Now I can speak Japanese and English. When I was mainly speaking Japanese, I did not express myself much to other people. It can be because of the circumstance I had or the culture I have. Then I started speaking English and learnt how to express myself, and came to know who I was, what I was aiming for in the future ... Now I'm back in Japan and my mind has started thinking in Japanese. Again, I seem to stop expressing myself. If I tell you which part of mine I like better, I prefer me speaking in English even though my Japanese is far better than my English.
For the self-study, the students may need to be given a couple of lessons off. The mini-essay, which should probably not 'count' for anything, is a useful practice for the assessment essays, and a chance to give them feedback on style etc.
Since many students find the latter sections of Whorf's passage rather difficult, one might suggest to them to read only as far as the heading "Grammatical Patterns ..."
The first and last paragraphs of the article from The Economist:
Can a concept exist without words to describe it?Take heart, those of you who struggled with maths at school. It seems that words for exact numbers do not exist in all languages. And if someone has no word for a number, he may have no notion of what that number means.
...The Pirahã are a people who have steadfastly resisted assimilation into mainstream Brazilian culture. Their commerce takes the form of barter, with no need to exchange money. Exact numbers do not exist in their language simply because there is no need for them. And in this case, what you do not need, you do not have. At least in the field of maths, it seems, Whorf was right.
Richard D. Gross, Psychology – The Science of Mind and Behaviour, 1987. Hodder and Stoughton. Chapters 4-6.
Nicky Hayes and Sue Orrell, Psychology – An Introduction, 1987. Longman. Chapters 4, 11, 12.
Keith Lehrer, Theory of Knowledge, 1990. Routledge. Chapter 3.
Top | Chapters | Home |